We
shall summarize the Orthodox position in theology, as
regards the “Filioque”, by making the following, basic
observations:
Firstly,
with regard to
Providence.
“Providence” implies the actions and the acts of God, within History and Creation. We too accept that the
Holy Spirit is given, is sent forth by the Son. So far,
at this level, the Filioque is acceptable. However, we cannot accept it from the aspect of the eternal, the
never-ending status of the Holy Trinity, where the
relations between the Persons are not relations that
pertain to any energies.
As far as
the eternal and never-ending Trinity is concerned, we
cannot accept that the Spirit also proceeds from
the Son, because inside the Trinity, we have ontological
relations only, and inevitably, the Cause can only be
one: the Father. Because, by introducing two Causes,
we will inevitably have two Gods.
In
Providence, one could say it is acceptable to admit that
the Spirit is also dependent on the Son; that it is a
gift, given to us by the Son. In this context, one can
speak in the same way that the Apostle Paul spoke, with
regard to the Spirit of Christ, i.e., that the Spirit
does indeed proceed from the Father, but, It is
sent forth, into Providence, via the Son.
The term “proceeding from” (åêðïñåýåôáé)
strictly pertains to the Spirit’s ontological
dependence on the Father, within the eternal
Trinity, therefore, the term “proceeding from” pertains
only to the eternal status of the Trinity. The
association here is strictly ontological, and the
Causer is only one: the Father.
When
dealing with Providence however, we do not touch on
ontological associations, but only those associations
that pertain to energies/actions, hence the Son’s
action of sending forth the Spirit. In
this way, we have a sort of Filioque, but only in
regard to Providence.
In light of
the above, significant confusion arose in the West, with
regard to these two terms.
The (Greek) words “åêðïñåýåôáé”
(
proceeding from/out of
)
and
“ðÝìðåôáé”
(
sent forth by
) were
translated in Latin, as
both meaning “procedure”,
right from the very start, in the 4th
century. This is what gave rise to the
confusion. They could not discern between these two
notions, whereas in the (Greek-speaking) East they were discernable, hence the term “proceeding from” (åêðïñåýåôáé)
was duly confined to the eternal, ontological aspect of
the Trinity, and was not used in reference to
Providence. From the very beginning, the Filioque was
applied by the West, to both aspects (ontological
and Providential). This is how the confusion began, and
the Filioque appeared as the offspring of precisely this
confusion. For the East, this distinction is
imperative; if one does make this distinction,
then he can accept the Filioque, but only in
regard to Providence. But the Filioque, in its true
dimensions as defined by the West, is not only linked to
Providence, but also to the eternal Trinity. And that is
where we have a problem. Can one apply the Filioque to
the eternal Trinity? Let’s observe the problems that
Patristic Theology encountered here.
In the 7th
century, Saint Maximus was asked (because word was
getting around that the Filioque was being used in the
West), what his opinion was on this matter. He replied
that he had examined the matter, and that the situation
was as follows:
The Latin-speaking
Romans
did not
have respective words for expressing these two notions
(“åêðïñåýåôáé”
and “ðÝìðåôáé”).
They used only one word. This consequently gave rise to
a confusion. We Greeks, who speak the language, must
therefore show some understanding in this regard and not
automatically declare the Filioque a heresy of the
Westerners, because, as analytically explained in the
“epistle to Marinus”, the Filioque was the product of
this confusion.
In the same
epistle, Saint Maximus says that during his talks with
the Romans themselves about this issue, he had noticed
that they also referred to Saint Cyril of Alexandria in
order to support the Filioque. Saint Cyril had indeed
written certain things that could have provided a basis
for the Filioque. We also have one testimony that
something which was written by Saint Cyril on the
subject had generated an intense reaction. It was the
reaction of Theodoretus of Cyrus who was quite strident
in his manner, and who commented that if Cyril was
referring to the Filioque in regard to Providence, then
all is well; but if he was relating it to the eternal
Trinity, then he was mistaken, and this could not be
accepted.
It was
obvious that Cyril did not mean it, simply and
strictly within the confines of Providence, as he had
also allowed inferences to the eternal Trinity.
He did not say “proceeds from” (åêðïñåýåôáé);
he did not use this word. He used the expression that
the Spirit is
manifested;
that it essentially originates (i.e., with regard to the
Essence) from the Son also.
Given that
the Essence is common to all three Persons, then the
Son must necessarily precede the Spirit, from the aspect
of the Essence. But, as for the Person of the
Spirit in connection to the other two Persons, we
cannot have the Filioque, because only the Father –as a
Person- can be the Cause. At first glance,
this
appears somewhat vague.
A passage
by Saint Gregory of Nyssa clarifies this vague point
somewhat satisfactorily.
In his work “That there are not three Gods” (üôé ïõê åéóß ôñåéò Èåïß),
he says:
«We
do not disregard the difference between that which
exists as the Cause, and that which is OF the
Cause». We
therefore have the Cause as one thing, and secondarily,
that which is OF the Cause. In other words, the
existence of God is not a simple thing; one cannot say
that God simply “exists”. God’s
existence
includes
activity,
movement.
Even
within God’s Being – within His ontological associations
–activity exists. God is not
devoid of
cause; He does not exist without cause. The cause is
naturally inside His very Self, but, there is a
distinction inside God: it is the distinction between
the Cause and whatever originates from the cause.
«We
support the difference between the One Who exists as the
Cause and the One who is OF the Cause».
It is in this way -and only in this way- that we can
perceive how the one Person is discerned from the
other; i.e., in the belief that the Cause is one, and
the other is OF the Cause. He further says that
«the
distinction between the Persons inside the Holy Trinity
cannot be made in any other way, except only in regard
to this causality.»
With
regard to the nature, with regard to the energy, we
cannot make such a distinction; however we can make it,
on the basis of this principle of causality. This is a
principle that was introduced by the Cappadocians.
Before them, we do not find it clearly
specified.
We
therefore have the ability to discern the Persons,
precisely because we make the distinction between the
Causer and that which is OF the Causer. And he continues:
«With
regard to that which is OF the Cause, we have in there
another distinction,
whereas with regard to the Cause, it is clear that it is
only the Father.
When referring to “OF the cause”, we can acknowledge a
further difference: That only the one of the two
originates
immediately
from the First».
He uses the word “immediately”, which implies
“directly”, or, “without any intermediation”.
«The
one originates immediately from the Cause, while the
other originates
through
(=with the
intermediation of)
the one who originates directly from the First».
The
difference between the Son and the Spirit –in regard to
the appearance, the existence and the origin of the two-
is that the Son comes forth
directly from
the Father (the Cause), while the Spirit comes forth
through the intermediation
of the one who originates directly from the Cause, i.e.,
via
the Son.
But why
does Gregory make this distinction and observation? He
goes on to explain, that
«Thus,
it is in this way, with this intermediation, this
intercession of the Son in the life of divinity, in
divine existence, that His characteristic of ‘Only-born’
is preserved»
So, in
order for the Son to remain “the Only-Born Son”, we must
attribute this “immediacy” to Him, otherwise we will
somehow end up with two Sons, albeit the natural, the
essential association of the Spirit with the Father is
not abolished, because all of divine nature also exists
within the Son, and consequently, in everything
essential (as regards the nature), the Spirit likewise
communes with the Father, even though it comes into
existence through the intermediation of the Son.
This could
be interpreted as a kind of Filioque from the aspect of
God’s eternal existence; however, neither the Son
nor the Spirit can be regarded as Causes.
In other words,
while the Son may in some way intercede for the Holy
Spirit to come into existence, this does not make
the Son the Causer of the Spirit. The Causer is
always the Father.
In
summarizing what we have said, we need to reach a
conclusion, because we have before us some very delicate
nuances. We need to maintain the principle -the faith-
that only the Father can be the Cause, and that the Son
–on account of the Filioque- can by no means be
perceived as a co-Causer of the Spirit’s existence.
Therefore,
from the aspect of Providence, there is no problem. From
the aspect of the eternality of the Trinity however, we
have the problem whether the intercession of the Son in
the procession of the Holy Spirit somehow makes the Son
the Cause of the Spirit, or not.
In his
epistle “To Marinus”, Saint Maximus stressed that he had
discussed the issue with the Romans of his time, and had
concluded that they did not imply that the Son is
the Causer. Thus, Maximus acquitted the Westerners of
the accusation of heresy. Of course, all of this had
taken place during the 7th century. Later
on, when the Filioque was used by the West as a banner
against the Orthodox, things changed, and they took a
different turn. In the discussions that took place, the
Westerners were no longer predisposed to revoking that
the Son is co-Causer along with the Father in the
“procession” of the Holy Spirit, thus reducing the
Filioque theory to a heresy, because it was not possible
to orthodoxically embrace it.
In the
Council of Florence, an attempt was made to unify the
division. It was through the use of the term “through
the Son”. If this had been accepted by both sides, then
instead of saying “from the Son”, we would have said
“through the Son” – in other words, it would have
connoted the intercession of the Son that Gregory
of Nyssa had mentioned. But even this attempt failed,
because neither side was willing to take a clear stance
on the issue, and the West had already stabilized its
own position with the expression “from the Father AND
the Son”, and was not willing in any way to retract it,
and replace it with the expression “THROUGH the Son”
Nowadays,
fresh attempts are being made, and it will prove very
interesting for one to observe where they will lead. As
Orthodox theologians, we must bear in mind that every
attempt –whatever it may involve, wherever it may lead-
should not lead us into the obscuring of the
basic premise that, within the Holy Trinity, ONLY THE
FATHER is the Cause.
An
idea has been proposed (mainly by a Russian theologian,
Bolotov, who has studied this subject especially) that
the Filioque should be regarded as something that can be
theologized. There is the distinction, which he
basically introduced, that there are many ideas which do
not constitute dogmas that affect man’s salvation. Some
of them that are regarded as topics for discussion, have
been considered items for theologizing, as opposed to
dogmas that are not items for theologizing, that should
not be subject to discussion.
So, there
is a proposal for the Filioque to be regarded as an item
to be theologized, but this is a proposal which was
not accepted, both by the Westerners and the East.
Because even the Westerners continue to maintain
(although nowadays they are tending to distance
themselves from this stance, whereas in the Middle Ages
they clearly supported it) that it is heresy for someone
to NOT believe in the Filioque, and that belief in the
Filioque comprises a dogma. Consequently, the idea of
the Filioque becoming an item to be theologized was not
accepted, and from time to time, it is brought up in
discussions of our time, along with Bolotov’s positions,
but there seems to be no progress in this direction.
Our
position should be that: provided the conditions we
mentioned above are applied, the Filioque can be
considered an item for theologizing. We in the East have
no need to introduce this, but, in the West they can use
it, provided that they mean it in the appropriate sense,
as they did in the 7th century. If they
regard it in a manner that makes the Son a co-Causer
together with the Father, then we cannot see this as an
item for theologizing, but as a heresy, because it
jeopardizes monarchy. That the Father alone is the
Causer, is linked to the fact that in God, we have only
one principality, and that this principality is
understood ontologically here. We do NOT have two
causes; we do NOT have two principalities. Since we have
a monarchy
(=one
principal),
we have only one cause, and that cause coincides with
the Father. Thus, literally, God is the Father. If we
introduce a second Causer (the Son), then we are at risk
of acknowledging two Gods.
The West
does not feel that it has this problem, because
“monarchy” to them is not the one Father, but the one
Essence. The
“one
God”
for
the Westerners is the one Essence, and not the Person of the Father. Consequently, they believe they are not
risking the loss of monotheism when they say “AND by the
Son”. For the West, monotheism is dependent on the one
essence of God, and not the Person of the
Father. And since this is the case, the Filioque does
not threaten their monotheism, because their monotheism
is not dependent on the notion of the “one Cause”.
We have
covered the topic of the Filioque,
having seen how it was generated historically, under
what premise it could have become accepted, at what
point it became a heresy, and at which points it could
constitute an item for theologizing.
OODE observation:
Obviously,
the fact that the official
Papist view does not
comprehend the issue of polytheism that springs from the
Filioque theory, does not mean that the problem
does not exist. On the contrary, because of this
differentiation, another, more serious problem is
apparent: That the Papists have in fact been
worshipping A DIFFERENT GOD than the one the Orthodox
Christians believe in.
While the Orthodox view is that “God is the Father”, the
Papist view is clearly that “God is an IMPERSONAL
ESSENCE”. Because, when the Person of the
Father is not regarded as the primary Cause, the
impersonal element of an alleged Triadic Essence is acknowledged in His place. This not only
undeniably ushers Papism into idolatry, but also, as we
have outlined in
previous chapters,
it has other, serious implications in the matter of
inter-Triadic relations between the Persons, and even
in what each Person is! The entire content of Theology
is distorted, and becomes totally unrecognizable.
Furthermore, by regarding the Essence as “God”, we no
longer have a subservience of the Essence to the
person, instead, the Person is subservient to the
Essence. In other words, the Father is no longer what
He is because He thus wills it, but because He is
compelled, by the Essence! The magnitude of
blasphemy that the Papist theory introduces with regard
to God, is clearly obvious here. We are shown a “God”
who is dependent
on His essence; a
SUBJUGATED GOD,
who functions on the basis of necessity and not on
freedom and free volition, exactly like the idolaters’
“gods” who are restricted within the confines of the
material universe, who are governed by “fate” and not by
the free will that they supposedly possess.
Secondary consequences of the above (so that we have a
better idea of the depth and the gravity of the issue)
are : Freedom –as a necessary ingredient for one’s
becoming “in the likeness of God”- is abrogated, and the
entire Christian dogma
on salvation thereafter collapses altogether,
dragging down with it the element of Love (since the
persons of Divinity are defined by the Essence and not
by voluntary love). We thus end up with the
god-judge-punisher of the West,
whom one can only fear and hate!
For all the aforementioned reasons (and many more, which
we do not need to expound here, because much has already
been outlined), which are all derived from the heretical
view on the “Essence God” of Augustine, it
becomes evident that not only should one not
agree to any union with the Papism that insists on
embracing the Filioque, but we should also demand from
them to relinquish altogether the Augustinian perception
of an “Essence God”, if they truly wish to be
re-incorporated in the Church of Christ.